РефератыИностранный языкEdEdward Carr And History Essay Research Paper

Edward Carr And History Essay Research Paper

Edward Carr And History Essay, Research Paper


Edward Hallett Carr’s contribution to the study of Soviet


history is widely regarded as highly distinguished. In all


probability very few would argue against this assessment of his


multi-volume history of Soviet Russia. For the majority of


historians he pretty much got the story straight. However, for


several years there was disagreement about his contribution to


the analytical philosophy of history. His ideas were outlined in What


is History? first published in 1961. For many today What


is History? is the most influential book on history thinking


published in Britain this century. For many years, however, the


methodologically foundationalist wing of the history profession


regarded the book as espousing a dangerous relativism. This has


now all changed. Arguably the central ideas in the book


constitute today’s mainstream thinking on British historical


practice. Most British commentators, if not that many in America,


acknowledge the significance and influence of the book. (l ) In


this review I want to establish why it is What is History?


now occupies a central place in British thinking about the


relationship between the historian and the past. I conclude that


the important message of What is History? – fundamentally


misconceived though I believe it to be – lies in its rejection of


an opportunity to re-think historical practice. This failure has


been most significant in rationalising the epistemologically


conservative historical thinking that pervades among British


historians today.


John Tosh, in the most recent edition of his own widely read


methodological primer The Pursuit of History describes


Carr’s book as “still unsurpassed as a stimulating and


provocative statement by a radically inclined scholar” (Tosh


1991: 234). Keith Jenkins, much less inclined to view Carr as a


radical scholar, never-the-less confirms the consequential nature


of What is History? suggesting that, along with Geoffrey


Elton’s The Practice of History both texts are still


popularly seen as “‘essential introductions’ to the ‘history


question”‘ (Jenkins 1995: 1-2). Jenkins concludes both Carr


and Elton “have long set the agenda for much if not all of


the crucially important preliminary thinking about the question


of what is history” (Jenkins 1995: 3).


So, according to Tosh and Jenkins, we remain, in Britain at


least, in a lively dialogue with What is History?. Why


should this be? The reason is, as most British historians know,


to be found in the position Carr took on the nature of historical


knowledge. A position that brought him into a long conflict with,


among others, the Tudor historian and senior Ambassador at the


Court of ‘Proper’ Objectivist History Geoffrey Elton. Again I


turn to John Tosh for his comment that “The controversy


between Carr and Elton is the best starting-point for the debate


about the standing of historical knowledge” (Tosh 1991:


236). Until Jenkins’ recent re-appraisal of Carr’s philosophy of


history, Carr had been misconstrued almost universally among


British historians as standing for a very distinctive relativist,


if not indeed a sceptical conception of the functioning of the


historian.


Explaining Carr’s ‘radicalism’ the philosopher of history


Michael Stanford has claimed Carr “insisted that the


historian cannot divorce himself from the outlook and interests


of his age (sic.)” (Stanford 1994: 86). Stanford quotes


Carr’s own claim that the historian “is part of


history” with a particular “angle of vision over the


past” (Stanford 1994: 86). As Stanford points out, Carr’s


“first answer…to the question ‘What is History?”‘ is


that it is a continuous “process of interaction between the


historian and his facts, an unending dialogue between the present


and the past”. While this was not a fresh insight with Carr,


it still carved him out for a number of years as someone with a


novel stance. However, over time, the effect of his argument


(which generated such initial notoriety) was to increasingly


balance the excesses of the hard core empiricists. In What is


History? Carr propelled British historiography toward a new


equilibrium – one that pivoted on a new epistemological


certitude.


The claim to epistemological radicalism on behalf of Carr does


not seem to me especially convincing. Why? My doubts about the


message in What is History? is the product of my present


intellectual situatedness as a historian (a writer about the


past). Today, with our greater awareness of the frailties and


failures of representationalism, referentialism, and inductive


inference, more and more history writing is based on the


assumption that we can know nothing genuinely truthful about the


reality of the past. It would be tempting, but wholly incorrect,


to say that history’s pendulum has swung far more to the notion


of history as a construction or fabrication of the historian.


Rather, what has happened, is that our contemporary conditions of


existence have created a much deeper uncertainty about the nature


of knowledge-creation and its (mis-)uses in the humanities. It is


not about swings in intellectual fashion.


It follows, a growing number of historians believe that we


don’t ‘discover’ (the truthful?’ ‘actual?’ ‘real?’ ‘certain?’)


patterns in apparently contingent events because, instead, we


unavoidably impose our own hierarchies of significance on them


(this is what we believe/want to see/read in the past). I do not


think many historians today are naive realists. Few accept there


must be given meaning in the evidence. While we may all agree at


the event-level that something happened at a particular time and


place in the past, its significance (its meaning as we narrate


it) is provided by the historian. Meaning is not immanent in the


event itself. Moreover, the challenge to the distinction of fact


and fiction as we configure our historical narratives, and


further acknowledgments of the cognitive power of rhetoric, style


and trope (metaphors are arguments and explanations) provide not


only a formal challenge to traditional empiricism, but forces us


to acknowledge that as historians we are making moral choices as


we describe past reality.


Does all this add up to a more fundamental criticism of


historical knowing than Carr imagined in What is History??


I think so. If this catalogue is what historical relativism means


today, I believe it provides a much larger agenda for the


contemporary historian than Carr’s (apparently radical at the


time) acceptance that the historian is in a dialogue with the


facts, or that sources only become evidence when used by the


historian. As Jenkins has pointed out at some length, Carr


ultimately accepts the epistemological model of historical


explanation as the definitive mode for generating historical


understanding and meaning (Jenkins 1995: 1-6, 43-63). This


fundamentally devalues the currency of what he has to say, as it


does of all reconstructionist empiricists who follow his lead.


This judgment is not, of course, widely shared by them. For


illustration, rather misunderstanding the nature of


“semiotics – the postmodern?” as he querulously


describes it, it is the claim of the historian of Latin America


Alan Knight that Carr remains significant today precisely because


of his warning a generation ago to historians to


“interrogate documents and to display a due scepticism as


regards their writer’s motives” (Knight 1997: 747). To


maintain, as Knight does, that Carr is thus in some way


pre-empting the postmodern challenge to historical knowing is


unhelpful to those who would seriously wish to establish Carr’s


contribution in What is History?. It would be an act of


substantial historical imagination to proclaim Carr as a


precursor of post-modernist history.


Carr is also not forgotten by political philosopher and critic


of post-modernist history Alex Callinicos, who deploys him


somewhat differently. In his defence of theory in interpretation


(Marxist constructionism in this case), Callinicos begins with


the contribution of a variety of so called relativist historians


of which Carr is one (others include Croce, Collingwood, Becker


and Beard). Acknowledging the “discursive character of


historical facts” (Callinicos 1995: 76) Callinicos quotes


Carr’s opinion (following Collingwood) that the facts of history


never come to us pure, but are always refracted through the mind


of the historian. For Callinicos this insight signals the problem


of the subjectivity of the historian, but doesn’t diminish the


role of empirically derived evidence in the process of historical


study.


Of course Carr tried to fix the status of evidence with his


own objections to what he understood to be the logic of


Collingwood’s sceptical position. Collingwood’s logic could,


claims Carr, lead to the dangerous idea that there is no


certainty or intrinsicality in historical meaning – there are


only (what I would call) the discourses of historians – a


situation which Carr refers to as “total scepticism” -


a situation where history ends up as “something spun out of


the human brain” suggesting there can be no “objective


historical truth” (Carr 1961: 26). Carr’s objectivist anchor


is dropped here. He explicitly rejected Nietzsche’s notion that


(historical?) truth is effectively defined by fitness for


purpose, and the basis for Carr’s opinion was his belief in the


power of empiricism to deliver the truth, whether it fits or not


(Carr 1961: 27). Historians ultimately serve the evidence, not


vice versa. This guiding precept thus excludes the possibility


that “one interpretation is as good as another” even


when we cannot (as we cannot in writing history) guarantee


‘objective or truthful interpretation’.


Carr wished to reinforce the notion that he was a radical. As


he said in the preface to the 1987 Second Edition of What is


History? “…in recent years I have increasingly come to


see myself, and to be seen, as an intellectual dissident’ (Carr


1987: 6). But his contribution really lies in the manner in which


he failed to be an epistemological radical. In the precise manner


of his return to the Cartesian and foundationalist fold lies the


importance of What is History? The book’s distinction


resides in its exploration and rapid rejection of epistemological


scepticism – what I call post-empiricism. From the first chapter


Carr accepts relativism would an unacceptable price to pay for


imposing the historian on the past beyond his narrow definition


of dialogue. Dialogue even cast as interrogation is all very well


and good, but an intervention that cannot ultimately become


objective is quite another matter. After all, Carr argues, it is


quite possible to draw a convincing line between the two.


While confirming the ever present interaction between the


historian and the events she is describing, Carr was ultimately


unwilling to admit that the written history produced by this


interaction could possibly be a fictive enterprise – historians


if they do it properly, (their inference isn’t faulty and/or they


don’t choose to lie about the evidence) will probably get the


story straight. This argument still appeals to many historians


today for whom the final defence against the relativism of


deconstructionism lies in the technical and forensic study of the


sources through the process of their authentication and


verification, comparison and colligation.


In Britain, most realist-inspired and empiricist historians


thus happily accept the logical rationalisation of Carr’s


position – that of the provisional nature of historical


interpretation. This translates (inevitably and naturally it is


argued) as historical revisionism (re-visionism?). The


provisionality of historical interpretation is a perfectly normal


and natural historian’s state-of-affairs that depends on


discovering new evidence (and revisiting old evidence for that


matter), treating it to fresh modes analysis and


conceptualisation, and constantly re-contextualising it. For


illustration, in my working career (since the early 1970s) the


omission of women in history has been ‘rectified’, and now has


moved through several historiographical layers to reach its


present highly sophisticated level of debate about the


possibility for a feminist epistemology(ies). So, new evidence


and new theories can always offer new interpretations, but


revisionist vistas still correspond to the real story of the past


because they correspond to the found facts.


In fact, with each revision (narrative version?) it is


presumed by some that we know better or see more clearly the


nature of the past. So, we are for ever inching our way closer to


its truth? Arthur Marwick makes the claim that by standing on


“…the powerful shoulders of our illustrious


predecessors” we are able both to advance “the


quality” and “the ‘truthfulness’ of history”


(Marwick 1970: 21). Standing on the shoulders of other historians


is, perhaps, a precarious position not only literally but also in


terms of the philosophy of history. No matter how extensive the


revisionary interpretation, the empiricist argument maintains


that the historical facts remain, and thus we cannot destroy the


knowability of past reality even as we re-emphasise or


re-configure our descriptions. Marxists and Liberals alike


sustain this particular non sequitur which means they can


agree on the facts, legitimately reach divergent interpretations


and, it follows, be objective. The truth of the past actually


exists for them only in their own versions. For both, however,


the walls of empiricism remain unbreached. The


(empiricist-inspired) Carr-endorsed epistemological theory of


knowledge argues that the past is knowable via the evidence, and


remains so even as it is constituted into the historical


narrative. This is because the ‘good’ historian is midwife to the


facts, and they remain sovereign. They dictate the historian’s


narrative structure, her form of argumentation, and ultimately


determine her ideological position.


For Carr, as much as for those who will not tarry even for the


briefest of moments with the notion of epistemological


scepticism, Hayden White’s argument that the historical narrative


is (a story) as much invented as found, is inadmissible because


without the existence of a determinate meaning in the evidence,


facts cannot emerge as aspects of the tru

th. Most historians


today, and l think it is reasonable to argue Carr also endorses


this view in What is History?, accept Louis Mink’s


judgment that “if alternative emplotments are based only on


preference for one poetic trope rather than another, then no way


remains for comparing one narrative structure with another in


respect of their truth claims as narratives” (Vann 1993: 1).


But Carr’s unwillingness to accept the ultimate logic of, in this


instance, the narrative impositionalism of the historian, and his


failure to recognise the representational collapse of history


writing, even as he acknowledges that “the use of language


forbids him to be neutral” (Carr 1961: 25), has helped blind


many among the present generation of British historians to the


problematic epistemological nature of the historical enterprise.


Take the vexed issue of facts. Carr’s answer to the question


“What is a historical fact?” is to argue, pace


Collingwood (Collingwood 1994: 245) that facts arise through


“…an a priori decision of the historian” (Carr


1961: 11). It is how the historian then arranges the facts as


derived from the evidence, and influenced by her knowledge of the


context, that constitutes historical meaning. For Carr a fact is


like sack, it will not stand up until you put ’something’ in it.


The ’something’ is a question addressed to the evidence. As Carr


insists, “The facts speak only when the historian calls on


them: it is he who decides to which facts to give the floor, and


in what order or context” (Carr 1961: 11).


It is easy to see why Elton and others like Arthur Marwick


misconstrue the (Collingwood-) Carr position when Carr says such


things because, if pushed a little further allows historians to


run the risk of subjectivity through their intervention in the


reconstruction of the past. Carr, of course, denies that risk


through his objectivist bottom line. There is clear daylight


between this position and that occupied by Hayden White. It is


that while historical events may be taken as given, what Carr


calls historical facts are derived within the process of


narrative construction. They are not accurate representations of


the story immanent in the evidence and which have been brought


forth (set free?) as a result of the toil, travail, and exertion


of the forensic and juridical historian.


Since the 1960’s Carr’s arguments have moved to a central


place in British thinking and now constitute the dominant


paradigm for moderate reconstructionist historians. This is


because, as Keith Jenkins has demonstrated, Carr pulls back from


the relativism which his own logic, as well as that of


Collingwood, pushes him. In the end Carr realises how close to


the postempiricist wind he is running, so he rejects


Collingwood’s insistence on the empathic and constitutive


historian, replacing her with another who, while accepting the


model of a dialogue between past events and future trends, still


believes a sort of objectivity can be achieved. This then is not


the crude Eltonian position. It is a claim to objectivity because


it is position leavened by a certain minimum self-reflexivity.


This is a conception of the role of the historian affirmed by the


most influential recent American commentators Joyce Appleby, Lynn


Hunt and Margaret Jacob who claim there can be no postmodern


history by repeating (almost exactly) Carr’s fastidious


empiricist position. Carr received only one oblique reference in


their book Telling the Truth About History which may help


explain why they re-packed Carr’s position as practical realism


(Appleby, Hunt and Jacob 1994: 237, 241-309 passim). Is it


that his position is so central to the intellectual culture of


mainstream history that it wasn’t even necessary to reference


him? In the early 1990’s the historian Andrew Norman endorsed the


Carr mainstream position more directly by arguing writing history


necessitates historians engaging directly with the evidence


“A good historian will interact dialogically with the


historical record” (Norman 1991: 132). Facts in history are


thus constituted out of the evidence when the historian


selects sources contextually in order to interpret and explain


that to which they refer, rather than in the narrative about


which they describe.


It is because Carr remains at the end of the day a convinced


objectivist despite (or because of?) his dalliance with


relativism – that his legacy in What is History? is still


so potent among British historians. His objectivist appeal in What


is History? is potent because it is not of the naive variety.


We know the Carr historian cannot stand outside history, cannot


be non-ideological, cannot be disinterested, or be unconnected to


her material because she is dispassionate. But she is telling us


what actually happened because she can overcome those obstacles.


She knows that the significance of the evidence is not


found solely in the evidence. The historian, as he said,


“does not deal in absolutes of this kind” (Carr 1961:


120). There can be no transcendental objective measures of truth.


However, while accepting the “facts of history cannot be


purely objective, since they become facts of history only in


virtue of the significance attached to them by the


historian” (Carr 1961: 120), Carr was forced by his naked


objectivist desire to underplay the problems of historical form


and the situatedness of the historian. he did this by arguing


that the standard for objectivity in history was the


historian’s “sense of the direction in history” by


which he meant the historian selected facts based not on personal


bias, but on the historian’s ability to choose “the right


facts, or, in other words, that he applies the right standard of


significance” (Carr 1961: 123).


Carr’s philosophical sleight-of-hand produced the objective


historian who “has a capacity to rise above the limited


vision of his own situation in society and history” and also


possesses the capacity to “project his vision into the


future in such a way as to give him a m-ore profound and more


lasting insight into the past than can be attained by those


historians whose outlook is entirely bounded by their own


immediate situation” (Carr 1961: 123). The objective


historian is also the historian who “penetrates most


deeply” into the reciprocal process of fact and value, who


understands that facts and values are not necessarily opposites


with differences in values emerging from differences of


historical fact, and vice versa. This objective historian also


recognises the limitations of historical theory. As Carr says a


compass “is a valuable and indeed indispensable guide. But


it is not a chart of the route” (Carr 1961: 116).


Social theory historians (constructionists) understand past


events through a variety of methods statistical and/or


econometric, and/or by devising deductive covering laws, and/or


by making anthropological and sociological deductive-inductive


generalisations. For hard-core reconstructionist-empiricists on


the other hand, the evidence proffers the truth only through


the forensic study of its detail without question-begging theory.


These two views are compromised by Carr’s insistence that the


objective historian reads and interprets the evidence at the same


time and cannot avoid some form of prior conceptualisation – what


he chooses simply (or deliberately loosely?) to call


“writing” (Carr 1961: 28). By this I think he means the


rapid movement between context and source which will be


influenced by the structures and patterns


(theories/models/concepts of class, race, gender, and so forth)


found, or discovered, in the evidence.


For Carr the evidence suggests certain appropriate explanatory


models of human behaviour to the objective historian which will


then allow for ever more truthful historical explanation. This


sleight-of-hand still has a certain appeal for a good number of


historians today. The American historian James D. Winn accepts


this Carr model of the objective historian when he says that


deconstructionist historians “…tend to flog extremely dead


horses” as they accuse other historians of believing history


is knowable, that words reflect reality, and their un-reflexive


colleagues still insist on seeing the facts of history


objectively. Few historians today, thanks to Carr, work from


these principles in pursuit of, as Winn says “…the


illusory Holy Grail of objective truth” but strive only to


ground “…an inevitably subjective interpretation on the


best collection of material facts we can gather” (Winn 1993:


867-68). At the end of the day, this position is not very much


different to the hard line reconstructionist-empiricist.


What Carr is doing then in What is History? is setting


up the parameters of the historical method – conceived on


the ground of empiricism as a process of questions suggested to


the historian by the evidence, with answers from the evidence


midwifed by the application to the evidence of testable theory as


judged appropriate. The appropriate social theory is a


presumption or series of connected presumptions, of how people in


the past acted intentionally and related to their social


contexts. For most objective historians of the Carr variety, his


thinking provides a more sympathetic definition of history than


the positivist one it has replaced, simply because it is more


conducive to the empirical historical method, and one which


appears to be a reasoned and legitimate riposte to the


deconstructive turn.


For such historians Carr also deals most satisfactorily with


the tricky problem of why they choose to be historians and write


history. The motivation behind the work of the historian is found


in the questions they ask of the evidence, and it is not,


automatically to be associated with any naked ideological


self-indulgence. Any worries of deconstructionists about either


ideology, or inductive inference, or failures of narrative form


has little validity so long as historians do not preconceive


patterns of interpretation and order facts to fit those


preconceptions. Carr would, I think, eagerly challenge the


argument that historians are incapable of writing down


(reasonably) truthful narrative representations of the past. The


position that there is no uninterpreted source would not be a


particularly significant argument for Carr because historians


always compare their interpretations with the evidence they have


about the subject of their inquiry. This process it is believed


will then generate the (most likely and therefore the most


accurate) interpretation.


So, when we write history (according to the Carr model) our


motivation is disinterestedly to re-tell the events of the past


with forms of explanation already in our minds created for us


through our prior research in the archive. ‘Naturally’ we are not


slaves to one theory of social action or philosophy of history -


unless we fall from objectivist grace to write history as an act


of faith (presumably very few of us do this? Do you do this?).


Instead we maintain our models are generally no more than


‘concepts’ which aid our understanding of the evidence indeed,


which grow out of the evidence. We insist our interpretations are


independent of any self-serving theory or master narrative


imposed or forced on the evidence. It is the ‘common sense’ wish


of the historian to establish the veracity and accuracy of the


evidence, and then put it all into an interpretative fine focus


by employing some organising concepts as we write it. We do it


like this to discover the truth of the past.


To conclude, Carr’s legacy, therefore, shades the distinction


between reconstructionism and constructionism by arguing we


historians do not go about our task in two separate ways with


research in the sources for the facts, and then offering an


interpretation using concepts or models of explanation. Rather


the historian sets off, as Carr says “…on a few of what I


take to be the capital sources” and then “inevitably


gets the itch to write”. This I take to mean to compose an


interpretation and “…thereafter, reading and writing go on


simultaneously” (Carr 1961; 28). For Carr this suggests the


“…untenable theory of history as an objective compilation


of facts…and an equally untenable theory of history as the


subjective product of the mind of the historian…” is much


less of a problem than any hard-nosed reconstructionists might


fear. It is in fact the way in which human beings operate in


everyday life, a “…reflection of the nature of man”


as Carr suggests. (Carr 1961: 29). Historians, like Everywoman


and Everyman work on the evidence and infer its most likely


meaning – unlike non-historians we are blessed with the


intellectual capacity to overcome the gravitational pull of our


earthly tethers.


The id e fixe of mainstream British historians today


is to accept history as this inferential and interpretative


process that can achieve truth through objectivism. Getting the


story straight (from the evidence). The unresolved paradox in


this is the dubious legacy of What is History?. I assume a


good number of historians recommend Carr to their students as the


starting point of methodological and philosophical


sophistication, and a security vouchsafed by the symmetry between


factualism, objectivism and the dialogic historian. While I am


unconvinced by its message, I think this is why What is


History? remains, for the majority of British historians, a


comforting bulwark against post-constructive and post-empirical


history.


References:


Appleby, Joyce, Hunt, Lynn, and Jacob, Margaret (1994) Telling


the Truth About History, W.W. Norton and Co., London.


Callinicos, Alex (1995) Theories and Narratives:


Reflections on the Philosophy of History, Cambridge, Polity


Press.


Carr, E.H. (1961) What is History? London, Penguin.


———— (1987) What is History? (Second Edition)


London, Penguin.


Collingwood R.G. (1994) The Idea of History (First


published 1946) Oxford, Oxford University Press.


Iggers, Georg, G. (1997) Historiography in the Twentieth


Century: From Scientific Objectivity to the Postmodern Challenge,


Hanover, NH, Wesleyan University Press.


Jenkins, Keith (1995) On ‘What is History?’, London,


Routledge.


———– (1997) Postmodern History Reader, London,


Routledge.


Knight, Alan (1997) “Latin Americ

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Edward Carr And History Essay Research Paper

Слов:4954
Символов:35265
Размер:68.88 Кб.