РефератыИностранный языкKaKarl Marx Essay Research Paper Essay on

Karl Marx Essay Research Paper Essay on

Karl Marx Essay, Research Paper


Essay on Karl Marx


Karl Heinrich Marx was the oldest surviving boy of nine children.


His father, Heinrich, a successful lawyer, was a man of the


Enlightenment, devoted to Kant and Voltaire, who took part in


agitations for a constitution in Prussia. His mother, born Henrietta


Pressburg, was from Holland. Both parents were Jewish and were


descended from a long line of rabbis, but, a year or so before Karl


was born, his father–probably because his professional career


required it–was baptized in the Evangelical Established Church.


Karl was baptized when he was six years old. Although as a youth


Karl was influenced less by religion than by the critical, sometimes


radical social policies of the Enlightenment, his Jewish background


exposed him to prejudice and discrimination that may have led him


to question the role of religion in society and contributed to his


desire for social change.


Marx was educated from 1830 to 1835 at the high school in Trier.


Suspected of harbouring liberal teachers and pupils, the school was


under police surveillance. Marx’s writings during this period


exhibited a spirit of Christian devotion and a longing for self-sacrifice


on behalf of humanity. In October 1835 he matriculated at the


University of Bonn. The courses he attended were exclusively in the


humanities, in such subjects as Greek and Roman mythology and the


history of art. He participated in customary student activities, fought


a duel, and spent a day in jail for being drunk and disorderly. He


presided at the Tavern Club, which was at odds with the more


aristocratic student associations, and joined a poets’ club that


included some political activists. A politically rebellious student


culture was, indeed, part of life at Bonn. Many students had been


arrested; some were still being expelled in Marx’s time, particularly


as a result of an effort by students to disrupt a session of the Federal


Diet at Frankfurt. Marx, however, left Bonn after a year and in


October 1836 enrolled at the University of Berlin to study law and


philosophy.


Marx’s crucial experience at Berlin was his introduction to Hegel’s


philosophy, regnant there, and his adherence to the Young


Hegelians. At first he felt a repugnance toward Hegel’s doctrines;


when Marx fell sick it was partially, as he wrote his father, “from


intense vexation at having to make an idol of a view I detested.” The


Hegelian pressure in the revolutionary student culture was powerful,


however, and Marx joined a society called the Doctor Club, whose


members were intensely involved in the new literary and


philosophical movement. Their chief figure was Bruno Bauer, a


young lecturer in theology, who was developing the idea that the


Christian Gospels were a record not of history but of human


fantasies arising from emotional needs and that Jesus had not been a


historical person. Marx enrolled in a course of lectures given by


Bauer on the prophet Isaiah. Bauer taught that a new social


catastrophe “more tremendous” than that of the advent of


Christianity was in the making. The Young Hegelians began moving


rapidly toward atheism and also talked vaguely of political action.


The Prussian government, fearful of the subversion latent in the


Young Hegelians, soon undertook to drive them from the


universities. Bauer was dismissed from his post in 1839. Marx’s


“most intimate friend” of this period, Adolph Rutenberg, an older


journalist who had served a prison sentence for his political


radicalism, pressed for a deeper social involvement. By 1841 the


Young Hegelians had become left republicans. Marx’s studies,


meanwhile, were lagging. Urged by his friends, he submitted a


doctoral dissertation to the university at Jena, which was known to


be lax in its academic requirements, and received his degree in April


1841. His thesis analyzed in a Hegelian fashion the difference


between the natural philosophies of Democritus and Epicurus. More


distinctively, it sounded a note of Promethean defiance:


Philosophy makes no secret of it. Prometheus’


admission: “In sooth all gods I hate,” is its own


admission, its own motto against all gods, . . .


Prometheus is the noblest saint and martyr in the


calendar of philosophy.


In 1841 Marx, together with other Young Hegelians, was much


influenced by the publication of Das Wesen des Christentums


(1841; The Essence of Christianity) by Ludwig Feuerbach. Its


author, to Marx’s mind, successfully criticized Hegel, an idealist


who believed that matter or existence was inferior to and dependent


upon mind or spirit, from the opposite, or materialist, standpoint,


showing how the “Absolute Spirit” was a projection of “the real man


standing on the foundation of nature.” Henceforth Marx’s


philosophical efforts were toward a combination of Hegel’s


dialectic–the idea that all things are in a continual process of change


resulting from the conflicts between their contradictory


aspects–with Feuerbach’s materialism, which placed material


conditions above ideas. (See dialectical materialism.)


In January 1842 Marx began contributing to a newspaper newly


founded in Cologne, the Rheinische Zeitung. It was the liberal


democratic organ of a group of young merchants, bankers, and


industrialists; Cologne was the centre of the most industrially


advanced section of Prussia. To this stage of Marx’s life belongs an


essay on the freedom of the press. Since he then took for granted


the existence of absolute moral standards and universal principles of


ethics, he condemned censorship as a moral evil that entailed spying


into people’s minds and hearts and assigned to weak and malevolent


mortals powers that presupposed an omniscient mind. He believed


that censorship could have only evil consequences.


On Oct. 15, 1842, Marx became editor of the Rheinische


Zeitung. As such, he was obliged to write editorials on a variety of


social and economic issues, ranging from the housing of the Berlin


poor and the theft by peasants of wood from the forests to the new


phenomenon of communism. He found Hegelian idealism of little use


in these matters. At the same time he was becoming estranged from


his Hegelian friends for whom shocking the bourgeois was a


sufficient mode of social activity. Marx, friendly at this time to the


“liberal-minded practical men” who were “struggling step-by-step


for freedom within constitutional limits,” succeeded in trebling his


newspaper’s circulation and making it a leading journal in Prussia.


Nevertheless, Prussian authorities suspended it for being too


outspoken, and Marx agreed to coedit with the liberal Hegelian


Arnold Ruge a new review, the Deutsch-franz sische Jahrb cher


(”German-French Yearbooks”), which was to be published in Paris.


First, however, in June 1843 Marx, after an engagement of seven


years, married Jenny von Westphalen. Jenny was an attractive,


intelligent, and much-admired woman, four years older than Karl;


she came of a family of military and administrative distinction. Her


half-brother later became a highly reactionary Prussian minister of


the interior. Her father, a follower of the French socialist


Saint-Simon, was fond of Karl, though others in her family opposed


the marriage. Marx’s father also feared that Jenny was destined to


become a sacrifice to the demon that possessed his son.


Four months after their marriage, the young couple moved to Paris,


which was then the centre of socialist thought and of the more


extreme sects that went under the name of communism. There,


Marx first became a revolutionary and a communist and began to


associate with communist societies of French and German


workingmen. Their ideas were, in his view, “utterly crude and


unintelligent,” but their character moved him: “The brotherhood of


man is no mere phrase with them, but a fact of life, and the nobility


of man shines upon us from their work-hardened bodies,” he wrote


in his so-called “+konomisch-philosophische Manuskripte aus dem


Jahre 1844″ (written in 1844; Economic and Philosophic


Manuscripts of 1844 [1959]). (These manuscripts were not


published for some 100 years, but they are influential because they


show the humanist background to Marx’s later historical and


economic theories.)


The “German-French Yearbooks” proved short-lived, but through


their publication Marx befriended Friedrich Engels, a contributor


who was to become his lifelong collaborator, and in their pages


appeared Marx’s article “Zur Kritik der Hegelschen


Rechtsphilosophie” (”Toward the Critique of the Hegelian


Philosophy of Right”) with its oft-quoted assertion that religion is the


“opium of the people.” It was there, too, that he first raised the call


for an “uprising of the proletariat” to realize the conceptions of


philosophy. Once more, however, the Prussian government


intervened against Marx. He was expelled from France and left for


Brussels–followed by Engels–in February 1845. That year in


Belgium he renounced his Prussian nationality.


Marx, Karl


Brussels period


The next two years in Brussels saw the deepening of Marx’s


collaboration with Engels. Engels had seen at firsthand in


Manchester, Eng., where a branch factory of his father’s textile firm


was located, all the depressing aspects of the Industrial Revolution.


He had also been a Young Hegelian and had been converted to


communism by Moses Hess, who was called the “communist rabbi.”


In England he associated with the followers of Robert Owen. Now


he and Marx, finding that they shared the same views, combined


their intellectual resources and published Die heilige Familie


(1845; The Holy Family), a prolix criticism of the Hegelian idealism


of the theologian Bruno Bauer. Their next work, Die deutsche


Ideologie (written 1845-46, published 1932; The German


Ideology), contained the fullest exposition of their important


materialistic conception of history, which set out to show how,


historically, societies had been structured to promote the interests of


the economically dominant class. But it found no publisher and


remained unknown during its authors’ lifetimes.


During his Brussels years, Marx developed his views and, through


confrontations with the chief leaders of the working-class


movement, established his intellectual standing. In 1846 he publicly


excoriated the German leader Wilhelm Weitling for his moralistic


appeals. Marx insisted that the stage of bourgeois society could not


be skipped over; the proletariat could not just leap into communism;


the workers’ movement required a scientific basis, not moralistic


phrases. He also polemicized against the French socialist thinker


Pierre-Joseph Proudhon in Mis re de la philosophie (1847; The


Poverty of Philosophy), a mordant attack on Proudhon’s book


subtitled Philosophie de la mis re (1846; The Philosophy of


Poverty). Proudhon wanted to unite the best features of such


contraries as competition and monopoly; he hoped to save the good


features in economic institutions while eliminating the bad. Marx,


however, declared that no equilibrium was possible between the


antagonisms in any given economic system. Social structures were


transient historic forms determined by the productive forces: “The


handmill gives you society with the feudal lord; the steammill, society


with the industrial capitalist.” Proudhon’s mode of reasoning, Marx


wrote, was typical of the petty bourgeois, who failed to see the


underlying laws of history.


An unusual sequence of events led Marx and Engels to write their


pamphlet The Communist Manifesto. In June 1847 a secret


society, the League of the Just, composed mainly of emigrant


German handicraftsmen, met in London and decided to formulate a


political program. They sent a representative to Marx to ask him to


join the league; Marx overcame his doubts and, with Engels, joined


the organization, which thereupon changed its name to the


Communist League and enacted a democratic constitution.


Entrusted with the task of composing their program, Marx and


Engels worked from the middle of December 1847 to the end of


January 1848. The London Communists were already impatiently


threatening Marx with disciplinary action when he sent them the


manuscript; they promptly adopted it as their manifesto. It


enunciated the proposition that all history had hitherto been a history


of class struggles, summarized in pithy form the materialist


conception of history worked out in The German Ideology, and


asserted that the forthcoming victory of the proletariat would put an


end to class society forever. It mercilessly criticized all forms of


socialism founded on philosophical “cobwebs” such as “alienation.”


It rejected the avenue of “social Utopias,” small experiments in


community, as deadening the class struggle and therefore as being


“reactionary sects.” It set forth 10 immediate measures as first steps


toward communism, ranging from a progressive income tax and the


abolition of inheritances to free education for all children. It closed


with the words, “The proletarians have nothing to lose but their


chains. They have a world to win. Workingmen of all countries,


unite!”


Revolution suddenly erupted in Europe in the first months of 1848,


in France, Italy, and Austria. Marx had been invited to Paris by a


member of the provisional government just in time to avoid


expulsion by the Belgian government. As the revolution gained in


Austria and Germany, Marx returned to the Rhineland. In Cologne


he advocated a policy of coalition between the working class and


the democratic bourgeoisie, opposing for this reason the nomination


of independent workers’ candidates for the Frankfurt Assembly and


arguing strenuously against the program for proletarian revolution


advocated by the leaders of the Workers’ Union. He concurred in


Engels’ judgment that The Communist Manifesto should be


shelved and the Communist League disbanded. Marx pressed his


policy through the pages of the Neue Rheinische Zeitung, newly


founded in June 1849, urging a constitutional democracy and war


with Russia. When the more revolutionary leader of the Workers’


Union, Andreas Gottschalk, was arrested, Marx supplanted him


and organized the first Rhineland Democratic Congress in August


1848. When the king of Prussia dissolved the Prussian Assembly in


Berlin, Marx called for arms and men to help the resistance.


Bourgeois liberals withdrew their support from Marx’s newspaper,


and he himself was indicted on several charges, including advocacy


of the nonpayment of taxes. In his trial he defended himself with the


argument that the crown was engaged in making an unlawful


counterrevolution. The jury acquitted him unanimously and with


thanks. Nevertheless, as the last hopeless fighting flared in Dresden


and Baden, Marx was ordered banished as an alien on May 16,


1849. The final issue of his newspaper, printed in red, caused a


great sensation.


Early years in London


Expelled once more from Paris, Marx went to London in August


1849. It was to be his home for the rest of his life. Chagrined by the


failure of his own tactics of collaboration with the liberal bourgeoisie,


he rejoined the Communist League in London and for about a year


advocated a bolder revolutionary policy. An “Address of the


Central Committee to the Communist League,” written with Engels


in March 1850, urged that in future revolutionary situations they


struggle to make the revolution “permanent” by avoiding


subservience to the bourgeois party and by setting up “their own


revolutionary workers’ governments” alongside any new bourgeois


one. Marx hoped that the economic crisis would shortly lead to a


revival of the revolutionary movement; when this hope faded, he


came into conflict once more with those whom he called “the


alchemists of the revolution,” such as August von Willich, a


communist who proposed to hasten the advent of revolution by


undertaking direct revolutionary ventures. Such persons, Marx


wrote in September 1850, substitute “idealism for materialism” and


regard


pure will as the motive power of revolution instead of


actual conditions. While we say to the workers: “You


have got to go through fifteen, twenty, fifty years of


civil wars and national wars not merely in order to


change your conditions but in order to change


yourselves and become qualified for political power,”


you on the contrary tell them, “We must achieve power


immediately.”


The militant faction in turn ridiculed Marx for being a revolutionary


who limited his activity to lectures on political economy to the


Communist Workers’ Educational Union. The upshot was that


Marx gradually stopped attending meetings of the London


Communists. In 1852 he devoted himself intensely to working for


the defense of 11 communists arrested and tried in Cologne on


charges of revolutionary conspiracy and wrote a pamphlet on their


behalf. The same year he also published, in a German-American


periodical, his essay “Der Achtzehnte Brumaire des Louis


Napoleon” (The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte), with


its acute analysis of the formation of a bureaucratic absolutist state


with the support of the peasant class. In other respects the next 12


years were, in Marx’s words, years of “isolation” both for him and


for Engels in his Manchester factory.


From 1850 to 1864 Marx lived in material misery and spiritual


pain. His funds were gone, and except on one occasion he could not


bring himself to seek paid employment. In March 1850 he and his


wife and four small children were evicted and their belongings


seized. Several of his children died–including a son Guido, “a


sacrifice to bourgeois misery,” and a daughter Franziska, for whom


his wife rushed about frantically trying to borrow money for a coffin.


For six years the family lived in two small rooms in Soho, often


subsisting on bread and potatoes. The children learned to lie to the


creditors: “Mr. Marx ain’t upstairs.” Once he had to escape them


by fleeing to Manchester. His wife suffered breakdowns.


During all these years Engels loyally contributed to Marx’s financial


support. The sums were not large at first, for Engels was only a


clerk in the firm of Ermen and Engels at Manchester. Later,


however, in 1864, when he became a partner, his subventions were


generous. Marx was proud of Engels’ friendship and would tolerate


no criticism of him. Bequests from the relatives of Marx’s wife and


from Marx’s friend Wilhelm Wolff also helped to alleviate their


economic distress.


Marx had one relatively steady source of earned income in the


United States. On the invitation of Charles A. Dana, managing


editor of The New York Tribune, he became in 1851 its European


correspondent. The newspaper, edited by Horace Greeley, had


sympathies for Fourierism, a Utopian socialist system developed by


the French theorist Charles Fourier. From 1851 to 1862 Marx


contributed close to 500 articles and editorials (Engels providing


about a fourth of them). He ranged over the whole political universe,


analyzing social movements and agitations from India and China to


Britain and Spain.


In 1859 Marx published his first book on economic theory, Zur


Kritik der politischen +konomie (A Contribution to the Critique


of Political Economy). In its preface he again summarized his


materialistic conception of history, his theory that the course of


history is dependent on economic developments. At this time,


however, Marx regarded his studies in economic and social history


at the British Museum as his main task. He was busy producing the


drafts of his magnum opus, which was to be published later as Das


Kapital. Some of these drafts, including the Outlines and the


Theories of Surplus Value, are important in their own right and


were published after Marx’s death.


Role in the First International


Marx’s political isolation ended in 1864 with the founding of the


International Working Men’s Association. Although he was neither


its founder nor its head, he soon became its leading spirit. Its first


public meeting, called by English trade union leaders and French


workers’ representatives, took place at St. Martin’s Hall in London


on Sept. 28, 1864. Marx, who had been invited through a French


intermediary to attend as a representative of the German workers,


sat silently on the platform. A committee was set up to produce a


program and a constitution for the new organization. After various


drafts had been submitted that were felt to be unsatisfactory, Marx,


serving on a subcommittee, drew upon his immense journalistic


experience. His “Address and the Provisional Rules of the


International Working Men’s Association,” unlike his other writings,


stressed the positive achievements of the cooperative movement and


of parliamentary legislation; the gradual conquest of political power


would enable the British proletariat to extend these achievements on


a national scale.


As a member of the organization’s General Council, and


corresponding secretary for Germany, Marx was henceforth


assiduous in attendance at its meetings, which were sometimes held


several times a week. For several years he showed a rare


diplomatic tact in composing differences among various parties,


factions, and tendencies. The International grew in prestige and


membership, its numbers reaching perhaps 800,000 in 1869. It was


successful in several interventions on behalf of European trade


unions engaged in struggles with employers.


In 1870, however, Marx was still unknown as a European political


personality; it was the Paris Commune that made him into an


international figure, “the best calumniated and most menaced man of


London,” as he wrote. When the Franco-German War broke out in


1870, Marx and Engels disagreed with followers in Germany who


refused to vote in the Reichstag in favour of the war. The General


Council declared that “on the German side the war was a war of


defence.” After the defeat of the French armies, however, they felt


that the German terms amounted to aggrandizement at the expense


of the French people. When an insurrection broke out in Paris and


the Paris Commune was proclaimed, Marx gave it his unswerving


support. On May 30, 1871, after the Commune had been crushed,


he hailed it in a famous address entitled Civil War in France:


History has no comparable example of such greatness.


. . . Its martyrs are enshrined forever in the great heart


of the working class.


In Engels’ judgment, the Paris Commune was history’s first example


of the “dictatorship of the proletariat.” Marx’s name, as the leader


of The First International and author of the notorious Civil War,


became synonymous throughout Europe with the revolutionary spirit


symbolized by the Paris Commune.


The advent of the Commune, however, exacerbated the


antagonisms within the International Working Men’s Association and


thus brought about its downfall. English trade unionists such as


George Odger, former president of the General Council, opposed


Marx’s support of the Paris Commune. The Reform Bill of 1867,


which had enfranchised the British working class, had opened vast


opportunities for political action by the trade unions. English labour


leaders found they could make many practical advances by


cooperating with the Liberal Party and, regarding Marx’s rhetoric


as an encumbrance, resented his charge that they had “sold


themselves” to the Liberals.


A left opposition also developed under the leadership of the famed


Russian revolutionary Mikhail Alexandrovich Bakunin. A veteran of


tsarist prisons and Siberian exile, Bakunin could move men by his


oratory, which one listener compared to “a raging storm with


lightning, flashes and thunderclaps, and a roaring as of lions.”


Bakunin admired Marx’s intellect but could hardly forget that Marx


had published a report in 1848 charging him with being a Russian


agent. He felt that Marx was a German authoritarian and an


arrogant Jew who wanted to transform the General Council into a


personal dictatorship over the workers. He strongly opposed


several of Marx’s theories, especially Marx’s support of the


centralized structure of the International, Marx’s view that the


proletariat class should act as a political party against prevailing


parties but within the existing parliamentary system, and Marx’s


belief that the proletariat, after it had overthrown the bourgeois


state, should establish its own regime. To Bakunin, the mission of


the revolutionary was destruction; he looked to the Russian


peasantry, with its propensities for violence and its uncurbed


revolutionary instincts, rather than to the effete, civilized workers of


the industrial countries. The students, he hoped, would be the


officers of the revolution. He acquired followers, mostly young men,


in Italy, Switzerland, and France, and he organized a secret society,


the International Alliance of Social Democracy, which in 1869


challenged the hegemony of the General Council at the congress in


Basel, Switz. Marx, however, had already succeeded in preventing


its admission as an organized body into the International.


To the Bakuninists, the Paris Commune was a model of


revolutionary direct action and a refutation of what they considered


to

be Marx’s “authoritarian communism.” Bakunin began organizing


sections of the International for an attack on the alleged dictatorship


of Marx and the General Council. Marx in reply publicized


Bakunin’s embroilment with an unscrupulous Russian student leader,


Sergey Gennadiyevich Nechayev, who had practiced blackmail and


murder.


Without a supporting right wing and with the anarchist left against


him, Marx feared losing control of the International to Bakunin. He


also wanted to return to his studies and to finish Das Kapital. At the


congress of the International at The Hague in 1872, the only one he


ever attended, Marx managed to defeat the Bakuninists. Then, to


the consternation of the delegates, Engels moved that the seat of the


General Council be transferred from London to New York City.


The Bakuninists were expelled, but the International languished and


was finally disbanded in Philadelphia in 1876.


Last years


During the next and last decade of his life, Marx’s creative energies


declined. He was beset by what he called “chronic mental


depression,” and his life turned inward toward his family. He was


unable to complete any substantial work, though he still read widely


and undertook to learn Russian. He became crotchety in his political


opinions. When his own followers and those of the German


revolutionary Ferdinand Lassalle, a rival who believed that socialist


goals should be achieved through cooperation with the state,


coalesced in 1875 to found the German Social Democratic Party,


Marx wrote a caustic criticism of their program (the so-called


Gotha Program), claiming that it made too many compromises with


the status quo. The German leaders put his objections aside and


tried to mollify him personally. Increasingly, he looked to a


European war for the overthrow of Russian tsarism, the mainstay of


reaction, hoping that this would revive the political energies of the


working classes. He was moved by what he considered to be the


selfless courage of the Russian terrorists who assassinated the tsar,


Alexander II, in 1881; he felt this to be “a historically inevitable


means of action.”


Despite Marx’s withdrawal from active politics, he still retained


what Engels called his “peculiar influence” on the leaders of


working-class and socialist movements. In 1879, when the French


Socialist Workers’ Federation was founded, its leader Jules Guesde


went to London to consult with Marx, who dictated the preamble


of its program and shaped much of its content. In 1881 Henry


Mayers Hyndman in his England for All drew heavily on his


conversations with Marx but angered him by being afraid to


acknowledge him by name.


During his last years Marx spent much time at health resorts and


even traveled to Algiers. He was broken by the death of his wife on


Dec. 2, 1881, and of his eldest daughter, Jenny Longuet, on Jan.


11, 1883. He died in London, evidently of a lung abscess, in the


following year.


Character and significance


At Marx’s funeral in Highgate Cemetery, Engels declared that


Marx had made two great discoveries, the law of development of


human history and the law of motion of bourgeois society. But


“Marx was before all else a revolutionist.” He was “the best-hated


and most-calumniated man of his time,” yet he also died “beloved,


revered and mourned by millions of revolutionary fellow-workers.”


The contradictory emotions Marx engendered are reflected in the


sometimes conflicting aspects of his character. Marx was a


combination of the Promethean rebel and the rigorous intellectual.


He gave most persons an impression of intellectual arrogance. A


Russian writer, Pavel Annenkov, who observed Marx in debate in


1846 recalled that “he spoke only in the imperative, brooking no


contradiction,” and seemed to be “the personification of a


democratic dictator such as might appear before one in moments of


fantasy.” But Marx obviously felt uneasy before mass audiences


and avoided the atmosphere of factional controversies at


congresses. He went to no demonstrations, his wife remarked, and


rarely spoke at public meetings. He kept away from the congresses


of the International where the rival socialist groups debated


important resolutions. He was a “small groups” man, most at home


in the atmosphere of the General Council or on the staff of a


newspaper, where his character could impress itself forcefully on a


small body of coworkers. At the same time he avoided meeting


distinguished scholars with whom he might have discussed questions


of economics and sociology on a footing of intellectual equality.


Despite his broad intellectual sweep, he was prey to obsessive ideas


such as that the British foreign minister, Lord Palmerston, was an


agent of the Russian government. He was determined not to let


bourgeois society make “a money-making machine” out of him, yet


he submitted to living on the largess of Engels and the bequests of


relatives. He remained the eternal student in his personal habits and


way of life, even to the point of joining two friends in a students’


prank during which they systematically broke four or five


streetlamps in a London street and then fled from the police. He was


a great reader of novels, especially those of Sir Walter Scott and


Balzac; and the family made a cult of Shakespeare. He was an


affectionate father, saying that he admired Jesus for his love of


children, but sacrificed the lives and health of his own. Of his seven


children, three daughters grew to maturity. His favourite daughter,


Eleanor, worried him with her nervous, brooding, emotional


character and her desire to be an actress. Another shadow was cast


on Marx’s domestic life by the birth to their loyal servant, Helene


Demuth, of an illegitimate son, Frederick; Engels as he was dying


disclosed to Eleanor that Marx had been the father. Above all,


Marx was a fighter, willing to sacrifice anything in the battle for his


conception of a better society. He regarded struggle as the law of


life and existence.


The influence of Marx’s ideas has been enormous. Marx’s


masterpiece, Das Kapital, the “Bible of the working class,” as it


was officially described in a resolution of the International Working


Men’s Association, was published in 1867 in Berlin and received a


second edition in 1873. Only the first volume was completed and


published in Marx’s lifetime. The second and third volumes,


unfinished by Marx, were edited by Engels and published in 1885


and 1894. The economic categories he employed were those of the


classical British economics of David Ricardo; but Marx used them


in accordance with his dialectical method to argue that bourgeois


society, like every social organism, must follow its inevitable path of


development. Through the working of such immanent tendencies as


the declining rate of profit, capitalism would die and be replaced by


another, higher, society. The most memorable pages in Das Kapital


are the descriptive passages, culled from Parliamentary Blue Books,


on the misery of the English working class. Marx believed that this


misery would increase, while at the same time the monopoly of


capital would become a fetter upon production until finally “the knell


of capitalist private property sounds. The expropriators are


expropriated.”


Marx never claimed to have discovered the existence of classes


and class struggles in modern society. “Bourgeois” historians, he


acknowledged, had described them long before he had. He did


claim, however, to have proved that each phase in the development


of production was associated with a corresponding class structure


and that the struggle of classes led necessarily to the dictatorship of


the proletariat, ushering in the advent of a classless society. Marx


took up the very different versions of socialism current in the early


19th century and welded them together into a doctrine that


continued to be the dominant version of socialism for half a century


after his death. His emphasis on the influence of economic structure


on historical development has proved to be of lasting significance.


Although Marx stressed economic issues in his writings, his major


impact has been in the fields of sociology and history. Marx’s most


important contribution to sociological theory was his general mode


of analysis, the “dialectical” model, which regards every social


system as having within it immanent forces that give rise to


“contradictions” (disequilibria) that can be resolved only by a new


social system. Neo-Marxists, who no longer accept the economic


reasoning in Das Kapital, are still guided by this model in their


approach to capitalist society. In this sense, Marx’s mode of


analysis, like those of Thomas Malthus, Herbert Spencer, or


Vilfredo Pareto, has become one of the theoretical structures that


are the heritage of the social scientist.


(L.S.F./D.T.McL.)


Durkhiem


Childhood and education.


Durkheim was born into a Jewish family of very modest means. It


was taken for granted that he would study to become a rabbi, like


his father. The death of his father before Durkheim was 20, which


burdened him with heavy responsibilities, and the increased rivalrous


tensions between France’s eastern provinces and Germany, may


have contributed to making Durkheim a severely disciplined young


man. As early as his late teens Durkheim became convinced that


effort and even sorrow are more conducive to the spiritual progress


of the individual than pleasure or joy.


His outstanding success at school designated him clearly as a


candidate to the renowned +cole Normale Sup rieure in Paris–the


most prestigious teachers’ college in France. While preparing for the


+cole Normale at the Lyc e Louis le Grand, Durkheim took his


board at the Institution Jauffret in the Latin Quarter, where he


became acquainted with another gifted young man from the


provinces, Jean Jaur s, later to lead the French Socialist Party and


at that time inclined like Durkheim toward philosophy and the


moral and social reform of his countrymen.


Durkheim passed the stiff competitive examination for the +cole


Normale one year after Jaur s, in 1879. It is clear that his religious


faith had vanished by then. His thought had become altogether


secular but with a strong bent toward moral reform. Like a number


of French philosophical minds during the Third Republic, he looked


to science and in particular to social science and to profound


educational reform as the means to avoid the perils of social


disconnectedness or “anomie,” as he was to call this condition in


which norms for conduct were either absent, weak, or conflicting.


(See anomie.)


He enjoyed the intellectual atmosphere of the +cole Normale–the


discussion of metaphysical and political issues pursued with


eagerness and animated by the utopian dreams of young men


destined to be among the leaders of their country. He soon enjoyed


the respect of his peers and of his teachers, but he was impatient


with the excessive stress then laid in French higher education on


elegant rhetoric and surface polish. His teachers of philosophy


struck him as too fond of generalities and of monotonous worship of


the past.


Fretting at the conventionality of formal examinations, he passed the


last competitive examination in 1882, but without the brilliance that


his friends had predicted for him. He then accepted a series of


provincial assignments as a teacher of philosophy at the state


secondary schools of Sens, Saint-Quentin, and Troyes between


1882 and 1887. In 1885-86 he took a year’s leave of absence to


pursue research in Germany, where he was impressed by Wilhelm


Wundt, pioneer experimental psychologist. In 1887 he was


appointed as lecturer at the University of Bordeaux, where he


subsequently became professor and taught social philosophy until


1902.


Analytic methods.


Durkheim was familiar with several foreign languages and reviewed


volumes in German, English, and Italian at length in the learned


journal L’Ann e Sociologique, which he founded in 1896. But it


has been noted, at times with disapproval and amazement, by


non-French social scientists, that he travelled little and that, like


many French scholars as well as the notable British anthropologist


Sir James Frazer, he never undertook any fieldwork. The vast


information he studied on the tribes of Australia or of New Guinea


or on the Eskimos was all collected by other anthropologists,


travellers, or missionaries.


This was not, in Durkheim’s case, due to provincialism or lack of


attention to the concrete. He did not resemble the French


philosopher Auguste Comte in making venturesome and dogmatic


generalizations and disregarding empirical observation. He did,


however, maintain that concrete observation in remote parts of the


world does not always lead to illuminating views on the past or even


on the present. To him facts had no meaning for the intellect unless


they were grouped into types and laws. He claimed repeatedly that


it is from a construction erected on the inner nature of the real that


knowledge of concrete reality is obtained, a knowledge not


perceived by observation of the facts from the outside. He thus


constructed concepts such as that of the sacred or of totemism,


exactly in the same way that Karl Marx developed the concept of


class.


In truth, Durkheim’s vital interest did not lie in the study for its own


sake of so-called primitive tribes, but rather in the light such a study


might throw on the present. The outward events of his life as an


intellectual and as a scholar may appear undramatic. Still, much of


what he thought and wrote stemmed from the events that he


witnessed in his formative years, in the 1870s and 1880s, and in the


earnest concern he took in them.


The Second Empire, which collapsed in the French defeat of 1870


at the hands of Germany, had seemed an era of levity and


dissipation to the earnest young Durkheim. France, with the


support of many of its liberal and intellectual elements, had plunged


headlong into a war for which it was unprepared; its leaders proved


incapable. The left-wing Commune that took over Paris after the


French defeat in 1871 led to senseless destruction, which appeared


to Durkheim’s generation, in retrospect, as evidence of the


alienation of the working classes from capitalist society.


The bloody repression that followed the Commune was taken as


further evidence of the ruthlessness of capitalism and of the


selfishness of the frightened bourgeoisie. Later, the crisis of 1886


over Georges Boulanger, minister of war, who demanded a


centralist government to execute a policy of revenge against


Germany, was one of several events that testified to the resurgence


of nationalism, soon to be accompanied by anti-Semitism. Such


major French thinkers of the older generation as Ernest Renan and


Hippolyte Taine interrupted their historical and philosophical works,


after 1871, to analyze those evils and to offer remedies.


Durkheim was one of several young philosophers and scholars,


fresh from their +cole Normale training, who became convinced that


progress was not the necessary consequence of the development of


science and technology, that it could not be represented by an


ascending curve, justifying complacent optimism. He perceived


around him the prevalence of “anomie,” a personal sense of


rootlessness fostered by the absence of social norms. Material


prosperity set free greed and passions that threatened the


equilibrium of society.


These sources of Durkheim’s sociological reflections, never remote


from moral philosophy, were first expressed in his very important


doctoral thesis, De la division du travail social (1893; The


Division of Labour in Society), and in Le Suicide (1897; Suicide).


In his view ethical and social structures were being endangered by


the advent of technology and mechanization. The division of labour


rendered workmen both more alien to one another and more


dependent upon one another, since none of them any longer built the


whole product by himself. Suicide appeared to be less frequent


where the individual was closely integrated with his culture; thus, the


apparently purely individual decision to renounce life could be


explained through social forces.


Effect of the Dreyfus affair.


These early volumes, and the one in which he formulated with


scientific rigour the rules of his sociological method, Les R gles de


la m thode sociologique (1895; The Rules of Sociological


Method), brought Durkheim fame and influence. But the new


science of society frightened timid souls and conservative


philosophers, and he had to endure many attacks. The Dreyfus


affair–resulting from the false charge against a Jewish officer, Alfred


Dreyfus, of spying for the Germans–erupted in the last years of the


century, and the slurs or outright insults aimed at Jews that


accompanied it opened Durkheim’s eyes to the latent hatred and


passionate feuds hitherto half concealed under the varnish of


civilization. He took an active part in the campaign to exonerate


Dreyfus. He was not elected to the Institut de France, although his


stature as a thinker suggests that he should have been named to that


prestigious, learned society. He was, however, appointed to the


University of Paris in 1902 and made a full professor there in 1906.


(See Dreyfus, Alfred.)


More and more, the sociologist’s thought became concerned with


education and religion as the two most potent means of reforming


humanity or of molding the new institutions required by the deep


structural changes in society. His colleagues admired Durkheim’s


zeal in behalf of educational reform. His efforts included participating


in numerous committees to prepare new curriculums and methods;


working to enliven the teaching of philosophy, which too long had


dwelt on generalities; and attempting to teach teachers how to teach.


A series of courses that he had given at Bordeaux on the subject of


L’+volution p dagogique en France (”Pedagogical Evolution in


France”) was published posthumously in 1938; it remains one of the


best informed and most impartial books on French education. The


other important work of Durkheim’s latter years dealt with the


totemic system in Australia and bore the title of Les Formes


l mentaires de la vie religieuse (1915; The Elementary Forms


of the Religious Life). The author, despite his own agnosticism,


evinced a sympathetic understanding of religion in all its stages.


French conservatives, who in the years preceding World War I


turned against the Sorbonne, which they charged was unduly


swayed by the prestige of German scholarship, railed at Durkheim,


who, they thought, was influenced by the German urge to


systematize, making a fetish of society and a religion of sociology.


(See “Elementary Forms of Religious Life, The”.)


In fact, Durkheim did not make an idol of sociology as did the


positivists schooled by Comte, nor was he a “functionalist” who


explained every social phenomenon by its usefulness in maintaining


the existence and equilibrium of a social organism. He did, however,


endeavour to formulate a positive social science that might direct


people’s behaviour toward greater solidarity.


The outbreak of World War I came as a cruel blow to him. For


many years he had expended too much energy on teaching, on


writing, on outlining plans for reform, on ceaselessly feeding the


enthusiasm of his disciples, and eventually his heart had been


affected. His gaunt and nervous appearance filled his colleagues with


foreboding. The whole of French sociology, then in full bloom


thanks to him, seemed to be his responsibility.


Death and legacy.


The breaking point came when his only son was killed in 1916,


while fighting on the Balkan front. The father stoically attempted to


hide his sorrow, but the loss, coming on top of insults by nationalists


who denounced him as a professor of “apparently German


extraction” who taught a “foreign” discipline at the Sorbonne, was


too much to bear. He died in November 1917.


Durkheim left behind him a brilliant school of researchers. He had


never been a tyrannical master; he had encouraged his disciples to


go farther than himself and to contradict him if need be. His nephew,


Marcel Mauss, who held the chair of sociology at the Coll ge de


France, was less systematic than Durkheim and paid greater


attention to symbolism as an unconscious activity of the mind.


Claude L vi-Strauss, who occupied the same chair of sociology and


resembles Durkheim in the way he combines reasoning with


intensity of feeling, also offered objections and corrections to


Durkheim’s views. With Durkheim, sociology had become in


France a seminal discipline that broadened and transformed the


study of law, of economics, of Chinese institutions, of linguistics, of


ethnology, of art history, and of history.


(H.M.P.)


|


collective behaviour


Individual motivation theories


Among the analytic theories that seek to eschew evaluation, the


most popular ones stress individual motivation in accounting for


collective behaviour. Frustration and lack of firm social anchorage


are the two most widely used explanations for individual


participation in collective behaviour of all kinds. In the psychiatric


tradition, frustration heightens suggestibility, generates fantasy, brings


about regressions and fixations, and intensifies drives toward wish


fulfillment so that normal inhibitions are overcome. Since most forms


of collective behaviour promote thoughts that are otherwise difficult


to account for and that breech behavioral inhibitions, this is often a


fruitful source of explanation.


In the sociological tradition of +mile Durkheim, absence of firm


integration into social groups leaves the individual open to deviant


ideas and susceptible to the vital sense of solidarity that comes from


participation in spontaneous groupings. Drawing upon both the


psychiatric and the sociological traditions, Erich Fromm attributed


the appeal of mass movements and crowds to the gratifying escape


they offer from the sense of personal isolation and powerlessness


that people experience in the vast bureaucracies of modern life.


Extending Karl Marx’s theory of modern man’s alienation from his


work, many contemporary students attribute faddism, crowds,


movements of the spirit, and interest-group and revolutionary


movements to a wide-ranging alienation from family, community,


and country, as well as from work. (See Marxism.)


According to the approach suggested by the U.S. political scientist


Hadley Cantril, participation in vital collectivities supplies a sense of


meaning through group affirmation and action and raises the


member’s estimate of his social status, both of which are important


needs often frustrated in modern society. Eric Hoffer, a U.S.


philosopher, attributed a leading role in collective behaviour to “true


believers,” who overcome their own personal doubts and conflicts


by the creation of intolerant and unanimous groups about them.


Crowds


A thin line separates crowd activities from collective obsessions.


The crowd is, first, more concentrated in time and space. Thus a


race riot, a lynching, or an orgy is limited to a few days or hours and


occurs chiefly within an area ranging from a city square or a stadium


to a section of a metropolitan area. Second, a concern of the


majority of the crowd (many participants do not always share the


concern) is a collaborative goal rather than parallel individual goals.


The “june bug obsession” cited earlier, in which dozens of women


went home from work because of imaginary insect bites, could have


turned into a crowd action if the women had banded together to


demand a change in working conditions or to conduct a ceremony


to exorcise the evil. Third, because the goal is collaborative, there is


more division of labour and cooperative activity in a crowd than in


collective obsessions. Finally, a major concern of a crowd is with


some improvement or social change expected as a result of its


activity. Labour rioters expect management to be more compliant


after the riot; participants in a massive religious revival expect life in


the community to be somehow better as a result.


The crucial step in developing crowd behaviour is the formation of a


common mood directed toward a recognized object of attention. In


a typical riot situation a routine police arrest or a fistfight between


individuals from opposing groups focuses attention. Milling and


rumour then establish a mood of indignation and hostility toward an


identified enemy or enemies. In a collective religious experience


there is usually an amazing event that rivets attention. Through


elementary collective behaviour the mood is defined as religious awe


and gratitude toward the supernatural and its agents.


As the mood and object become established, either an “active”


crowd or an “expressive” crowd is formed. The active crowd is


usually aggressive, such as a violent mob, though occasionally it acts


to propel members into heroic accomplishments. The expressive


crowd has also been called the dancing crowd because its


manifestations are dancing, singing, and other forms of emotional


expression.

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Karl Marx Essay Research Paper Essay on

Слов:8742
Символов:61358
Размер:119.84 Кб.