Summary Of Kant

’s Life Essay, Research Paper


Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) spent all of his life in K?nigsberg, a


small German town on the Baltic Sea in East Prussia. (After World War II,


Germany’s border was pushed west, so K?nigsberg is now called


Kaliningrad and is part of Russia.) At the age of fifty-five, Kant appeared to


be a washout. He had taught at K?nigsberg University for over twenty


years, yet had not published any works of significance.


During the last twenty-five years of his life, however, Kant left a


mark on the history of philosophy that is rivaled only by such towering


giants as Plato and Aristotle. Kant’s three major works are often


considered to be the starting points for different branches of modern


philosophy: the Critique of Pure Reason (1781) for the philosophy of


mind; the Critique of Practical Reason (1788) for moral philosophy; and


the Critique of Judgment (1790) for aesthetics, the philosophy of art.


The Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals was published in


1785, just before the Critique of Practical Reason. It is essentially a short


introduction to the argument presented in the second Critique. In order to


understand what Kant is up to in this book, it is useful to know something


about Kant’s other works and about the intellectual climate of his time.


Kant lived and wrote during a period in European intellectual history


called the “Enlightenment.” Stretching from the mid-seventeenth century to


the early nineteenth, this period produced the ideas about human rights and


democracy that inspired the French and American revolutions. (Some other


major figures of the Enlightenment were Locke, Hume, Rousseau, and


Leibniz.)


The characteristic quality of the Enlightenment was an immense


confidence in “reason”–that is, in humanity’s ability to solve problems


through logical analysis. The central metaphor of the Enlightenment was a


notion of the light of reason dispelling the darkness of mythology and


misunderstanding. Enlightenment thinkers like Kant felt that history had


placed them in the unique position of being able to provide clear reasons


and arguments for their beliefs. The ideas of earlier generations, they


thought, had been determined by myths and traditions; their own ideas were


based on reason. (According to this way of thinking, the French monarchy’s


claims to power were based on tradition; reason prescribed a republican


government like that created by the revolution.)


Kant’s philosophical goal was to use logical analysis to understand


reason itself. Before we go about analyzing our world, Kant argued, we


must understand the mental tools we will be using. In the Critique of Pure


Reason Kant set about developing a comprehensive picture of how our


mind–our “reason”– receives and processes information.


Kant later said that the great Scottish philosopher David Hume


(1711-76) had inspired him to undertake this project. Hume, Kant said,


awoke him from an intellectual “slumber.” The idea that so inspired Kant


was Hume’s analysis of cause-and-effect relationships. When we talk about


events in the world, Hume noted, we say that one thing “causes” another.


But nothing in our perceptions tells us that anything causes anything else. All


we know from our perceptions is that certain events regularly occur


immediately after certain other events. “Causation” is a concept that we


employ to make sense of why certain events regularly follow certain other


events.


Kant took Hume’s idea and went one step further. Causation, Kant


argues, is not just an idea that we employ to make sense of our


perceptions. It is a concept that we cannot help but employ. We don’t sit


around watching events and then develop an idea of causation on the basis


of what we see. When we see a baseball break a window, for instance, we


don’t need to have seen balls break windows before to say that the ball


“caused” the window to break; causation is an idea that we automatically


bring to bear on the situation. Kant argued that causation and a number of


other basic ideas–time and space, for instance–are hardwired, as it were,


into our minds. Anytime we try to understand what we see, we cannot help


but think in terms of causes and effe

cts.


Kant’s argument with Hume may seem like hairsplitting, but it has


huge implications. If our picture of the world is structured by concepts that


are hardwired into our minds, then we can’t know anything about how the


world “really” is. The world we know about is developed by combining


sensory data (”appearances” or “phenomena,” as Kant called them) with


fundamental concepts of reason (causation, etc.). We don’t know anything


about the “things-in- themselves” from which sensory data emanates. This


recognition that our understanding of the world may have as much to do


with our minds as with the world has been called a “Copernican Revolution”


in philosophy–a change in perspective as significant to philosophy as


Copernicus’ recognition that the earth is not the center of the universe.


Kant’s insights posed a severe challenge to many earlier ideas.


Before Kant, for instance, many philosophers offered “proofs” of the


existence of God. One argument made was that there must be a “first


cause” for the universe. Kant pointed out that we can either imagine a world


in which some divine being set the universe in motion, causing all later


events; or we can imagine a universe that is an infinite series of causes and


effects extending endlessly into the past and future. But since causation is an


idea that comes from our minds and not from the world, we cannot know


whether there “really” are causes and effects in the world–let alone whether


there was a “first cause” that caused all later events. The question of


whether there “must” be a first cause for the universe is irrelevant, because it


is really a question about how we understand the world, not a question


about the world itself.


Kant’s analysis similarly shifted the debate over “free will” and


“determinism.” (Kant presents a version of this argument in Chapter 3 of the


Grounding.) Human beings believe that they have “free will”; we feel as


though we may freely choose to do whatever we like. At the same time,


however, the world that we experience is a world of causes and effects;


everything we observe was caused by whatever preceded it. Even our own


choices appear to have been caused by prior events; for instance, the


choices you make now are based on values you learned from your parents,


which they learned from their parents, and so forth. But how can we be free


if our behavior is determined by prior events? Again, Kant’s analysis shows


that this is an irrelevant question. Anytime we analyze events in the world,


we come up with a picture that includes causes and effects. When we use


reason to understand why we have made the choices we have, we can


come up with a causal explanation. But this picture isn’t necessarily


accurate. We don’t know anything about how things “really” are; we are


free to think that we can make free choices, because for all we know this


might “really” be the case.


In the Critique of Practical Reason and the Grounding for the


Metaphysics of Morals, Kant applies this same technique–using reason to


analyze itself–to determine what moral choices we should make. Just as we


cannot rely on our picture of the world for knowledge about how the world


“really” is, so can we not rely on expectations about events in the world in


developing moral principles. Kant tries to develop a moral philosophy that


depends only on the fundamental concepts of reason.


Some later scholars and philosophers have criticized Enlightenment


philosophers like Kant for placing too much confidence in reason. Some


have argued that rational analysis isn’t the best way to deal with moral


questions. Further, some have argued that Enlightenment thinkers were


pompous to think that they could discover the timeless truths of reason; in


fact, their ideas were determined by their culture just as all other people’s


are. Some experts have gone as far as to associate the Enlightenment with


the crimes of imperialism, noting a similarity between the idea of reason


dispelling myth and the idea that Western people have a right and a duty to


supplant less “advanced” civilizations. As we work through the Grounding


for the Metaphysics of Morals, we will return to such criticisms as they


apply to Kant.

Сохранить в соц. сетях:
Обсуждение:
comments powered by Disqus

Название реферата: Summary Of Kant

Слов:1513
Символов:10059
Размер:19.65 Кб.